Every -calculus Term Has a Size
In this example we will discuss schema subsumption, a capability in Adelfa which allows one to “transport” a formula with a context variable typed by one context schema to a different context schema.
The complete developments are provided here for reference:
- Signature:
size.lf
- Proof development without transport:
size-no-transport.ath
- Proof development with transport:
size-transport.ath
This becomes especially useful when using lemmas.
To show the usefulness of schema subsumption, we formalize a specification for the size of lambda calculus terms and prove that every term has a size. The informal rules for the size of terms is:
Where ranges over terms and denotes a variable.
Before we can specify the size judgements in LF, we have to specify natural numbers and addition. We have seen these specified in first order examples so will limit the discussion here to a presentation of the specification.
nat : type.
z : nat.
s : {x:nat} nat.
plus : {x1:nat}{x2:nat}{x3:nat} type.
plus-z : {x: nat} plus z x x.
plus-s : {x1:nat}{x2:nat}{x3:nat}
{D: plus x1 x2 x3} plus (s x1) x2 (s x3).
Natural numbers and addition are common enough relations that we would want to have a standard library1 which defines them along with its properties. Foreseeing our eventual proof, we introduce a single theorem which states “for any two natural numbers, there exists a natural number which is their sum.”
Theorem plus-exist : forall N1 N2,
{N1: nat} => {N2:nat} => exists N3 D, {D: plus N1 N2 N3}
induction on 1
intros
case H1
apply IH to H3 H2
exists s N3
exists plus-s x N2 N3 D
search
exists N2
exists plus-z N2 search
With this standard library now in place, we can specify our -calculus terms and their size. Their specification is a straightforward translation from our informal rules.
tm : type.
app : {E1:tm}{E2:tm} tm.
lam : {E: {x:tm} tm} tm.
size : {E:tm}{x:nat} type.
size-lam : {E: {y:tm} tm}{X:nat}
{D:{x:tm} {dx: size x (s z)} size (E x) X}
size (lam ([x] E x)) (s X).
size-app : {E1:tm}{E2:tm}{X1:nat}{X2:nat}{X3:nat}
{D1: size E1 X1}
{D2: size E2 X2}
{D3: plus X1 X2 X3}
size (app E1 E2) (s X3).
Before we walk through our goal of showing every term has a size in Adelfa, let’s walk through the informal proof.
Theorem: Every -calculus term has a size .
Proof: By induction on the size of terms. Case analysis on :
- If is a variable, by definition
- If is , by inductive hypothesis, there is some such that . By definition,
- If is , then by inductive hypothesis on the component terms, there is some and such that and . By definition,
Q.E.D.
When proving this in Adelfa, we must be more precise about our statement. We
permit open terms in our informal proof and categorize all variables as having a
size of . This doesn’t suffice in a formal setting, so we limit ourselves
to closed terms and prove our statement for terms under a context which forces
the size of terms to be assessed under a context with variables of size 1. This is
encoded within the size-lam
term constructor. Reasoning inductively over
derivations of size
then results in a regular shape for contexts:
We specify such a shape in adelfa by defining a context schema C
, with which we
we lay out the entries of a single repetition.
Schema C := (x: tm, y: size x (s z)).
Our proof in Adelfa aligns closely with our informal proof. We begin by
performing induction on the derivation of the of E
, introducing the
eigenvariables, context variable, and implication as hypotheses, then performing
case analysis on the derivation of E
. Our first proof obligation is that of an
abstraction. To keep this example concise, we will skip the proof of the
abstraction and move into the more interesting case of an application.
Theorem tm-has-size : ctx G:C, forall E,
{G |- E : tm} => exists N D, {G |- D: size E N}
induction on 1 intros
case H1 (keep) skip
To complete the application case, we apply the inductive hypothesis to the
assumptions {G |- E1 : tm}
and {G |- E2 : tm}
.
apply IH to H2 apply IH to H3
We want to instantiate the existentially quantified N
with the successor of
the sum for N
and N1
, but we are missing a derivation for the sum. In our
library, we have a proof of this plus-exist
. Let’s get derivations for these
natural numbers and attempt to utilize this lemma.
assert { G |- N : nat }
assert { G |- N1 : nat }
apply plus-exist to H6 H7
The resulting error “Error: could not match context variables” arises because
plus-exist
was proven for LF derivations without any context variable. As
such, Adelfa cannot verify the proof still holds in the presence of this context
variable. In the next section we’ll walk through, step by step, how one may
attempt to fix this situation and discuss them.
Proof Without Transport
In this section, we will discuss two ways to continue this proof without utilizing the transport rule and see where approaches differ and where they fall short.
Removing context dependencies
The first solution one may try is to prove that the natural numbers do not rely
on entries in the schema C
to use this lemma. Such a proof is fairly routine
by induction and case analysis on the derivation for natural numbers.
Theorem nat-ind : ctx G:C, forall N,
{ G |- N : nat } => { N : nat }
induction on 1 intros
case H1 apply IH to H2 search search
Let’s back up to when we tried to use plus-exist
and try to complete the proof
after removing the context variables. This time, the application of plus-exist
is allowed, and now have an assumption for {D2 : plus N N1 N3}
.
assert { G |- N : nat } apply nat-ind to H6
assert { G |- N1 : nat } apply nat-ind to H8
apply plus-exist to H7 H9
Given N3
is the sum of the sizes for E1
and E2
, the goal’s existentially
quantified variables can now be instantiated with N
as (s N3)
and D
as a
term constructor for size-app
. This time, we cannot complete the case since
adelfa cannot find a derivation for:
exists (s N3)
exists size-app E1 E2 N N1 N3 D D1 D2
search
In order to utilize size-app
we must have N3
under the same context variable
as the other terms. Yet, our only occurrence of N3
in our assumption set is
within the formula {D2 : plus N N1 N3}
. The best Adelfa can deduce is
therefore {N3 : nat}
. One may try to prove a lemma of the sort:
Theorem nat-wk : ctx G:C, forall N, { N : nat } => { G |- N : nat}.
But this will not work. The instantiations for G
are not limited to
well-formed ones, and therefore this statement is false. Therefore, the state we
are in within our proof of tm-has-size
has reached a dead end, and we must
reevaluate how to proceed.
Reproving lemmas
The second approach one may attempt is to reprove necessary lemmas under a context variable.
Theorem plus-exist-context : ctx G:C, forall N1 N2,
{G |- N1: nat} => {G |- N2:nat} => exists N3 D, {G |- D: plus N1 N2 N3}
induction on 1
intros
case H1
apply IH to H3 H2
exists s N3
exists plus-s x N2 N3 D
search
exists N2
exists plus-z N2 search
Notice that there is no difference in the proof compared to the one without
the context variable. This makes sense, because nat
and plus
do not depend on anything within G
.
Using this reproved lemma within our proof of tm-has-size
will succeed this
time.
assert { G |- N : nat }
assert { G |- N1 : nat }
apply plus-exist-context to H6 H7
Having an assumption formula {G |- D2 : plus N N1 N3}
allows us to properly
instantiate the existentially quantified variables with N
as s N3
and D
as
the term constructor size-app
. This case can then be completed and we can move
on to the next proof obligation. Our previous issue where we could not show that
N3
is a wellformed term of type nat
in the contxt G
. This is no longer an
issue now that we have the assumption {G |- D2 : plus N N1 N3}
, which implies
{G |- N3 : nat}
.
exists (s N3)
exists size-app E1 E2 N N1 N3 D D1 D2
Proof With Transport
With schema subsumption, when Adelfa encounters a usage of the apply
tactic
which would fail due to a mismatch in context schemas, it will automatically try
to transport the proof into the new context schema. In our case, transporting
the proof of plus-exist
into one of
plus-exist-context
automatically.
The proof for tm-has-size
then requires no extra lemmas and can directly
utilize the library’s theorem without worrying about reproving routine
properties under a new context schema.
assert { G |- N : nat }
assert { G |- N1 : nat }
apply plus-exist to H6 H7
exists (s N3)
exists size-app E1 E2 N N1 N3 D D1 D2
search
With transport, the entire proof is:
Theorem tm-has-size : ctx G:C, forall E,
{G |- E : tm} => exists N D, {G |- D: size E N}
induction on 1 intros
case H1 (keep)
weaken H2 with size n (s z)
apply IH to H3 with (G = G, n1:tm, n:size n1 (s z))
assert { G, n1:tm, n:size n1 (s z) |- N n1 n : nat }
prune H5 strengthen H5 strengthen H6
exists (s N) exists size-lam ([x] E1 x) N D
search
apply IH to H2 apply IH to H3
assert { G |- N : nat } assert { G |- N1 : nat }
apply plus-exist to H6 H7
exists (s N3) exists size-app E1 E2 N N1 N3 D D1 D2 search
exists (s z) exists n1 search
Footnotes
-
Adelfa does not currently have the ability to compose specifications or theorem developments which would permit libraries, so we inline these portions in lieu of this feature. ↩